#2 = Volume 1, Part 2 = Fall 1973
Stanislaw Lem
Remarks Occasioned by Dr. Plank's Essay
"Quixote's Mills"
According to our cultural tradition a literary work, is significant in the
degree to which it differs in a nontrivial way from all previously published
works. This individualistic approach, strongly correlated with the concept of
the uniqueness of each literary work, is perhaps dying out in our time, for it
is opposed to the trend of mass culture.
A literary work is at the same time something strange and something familiar.
Thanks to its familiarity we can understand it well; thanks to its strangeness
we can experience through its content a new revelation of what we had thought to
be banalized, doomed to silence. Neither the strangeness alone nor the
familiarity alone can make a work of art relevant: the fusion of the two is the
necessary precondition of creation.
From a bird's-eye view, the whole domain of modern literature is somewhat
depressing. Mainstream writing tells us all about practically nothing, and SF
tells us practically nothing about all. The mainstream bores us with everyday
trivia as seen through a magnificent microscope-- the magnificent system of
well-focused lenses created by the self-devouring sophistication of hyperspecialized narrative modes. In SF we look through a badly built apparatus
at "all"--but this "all" is dubious if not falsified. We
have in SF a
counterfeited Cosmos,
a nauseating mixture anachronisms,
counter-empirical as a whole, and an
oversimplified future of the
race, perceived only at its black extremes, only in the spectrum of all
imaginable holocausts and global suicides; and what stands in SF for human
reason is really only a moronized superman version. In SF we do not even see
the big problems central to future research (future social structures, the
relationship of man to artificial man, mankind endangering itself with the not
yet evident consequences of so-called progress) other than through a dimmed
glass, darkly: the whole apparatus is out of focus--and intentionally so.
This intentionality must be explained before we can proceed. Our neighbor
planets, Mars and Venus, were thought by the old time astronomers to be images of
Earth's future (Mars) or of its past (Venus). We know now that neither of these
assumptions is true. Venus is not similar to Earth as Earth was some hundreds of
millions of years ago, and Mars has nothing in common with the planet imagined
by astronomers--a planet on which the once vigorous life forms were dying out,
being involved in an heroic but already lost struggle with worsening
environmental conditions (the "canals" were thought to be signs of
this struggle, with respect to the supply of water). So we see that for the
old time astronomers these planets were a kind of Rorschach test: they did not
see the planets as they really were; they did not stop at the limit of their
knowledge based on observational facts; they instead projected their
unconscious, anthropocentric expectations into outer space, building a coherent,
intelligible system of relations, a spectrum of celestial bodies in which
Earth's position was still central, thus repeating the error of pre-Copernican cosmology. The parallel looks like this: Venus has not YET achieved, and Mars
has ALREADY lost, what Earth NOW possesses. This invariant of our perception
manifests itself in science only unintentionally, for the sole task of
science is to build a model of reality as true as possible. Since the task of
science is unambiguous, the attitude of the scientist has little in common with
that of the writer, for whereas there is a licentia poetica, there is no
such thing as licentia scientifica.
Although the distortion of the world's image is possible in science only as
an error, such distortion in literature is often the proper mode of individual
expression. But not every kind of intentional distortion and transformation of
true facts is of the same value in literature. Highly specialized distortions,
or rather their modi in a paradigmatical sense, are selected out of the set of
"all possible distortions" by the process of evolution in the various
literary genres. This selection is by no means a rational progress, for the
writers themselves do not know why this rather than that transformational
pattern of the narrative becomes a leading paradigm of creation. Nevertheless
Occam's razor is in a way valid in belles lettres. It can be called the minimax tactics of creation: the greatest impact results from a minimum of
invested means--a very old maxim, put by J.W. Goethe in the words "In der
Beschrinkung zeigt sich erst der Meister." The neglect of this rule results
in an inflationary escalation of means and meanings.
While the real universe is a thing too big for our science (and will remain
so forever, I think), it is too small and too crowded a place for the expansion
of escapist dreams, so SF has invented a lot of other universes. But this remark
is only preliminary; the heart of the matter is inflation in art, and
specifically in SF. The generally low standard of SF is often defended with an
expression now proverbial in SF circles, that "90% of everything is
trash." But this defense is not only inappropriate; it misses the point
central to any discussion of the genre.
In the realm of art we are accustomed to the state of things in which a
hierarchical order builds up with the passing of time. The best works find their
place at the top of the pyramid, and the hopeless misconstructions find theirs
at the bottom. This process of ordering goes on very slowly; as the device
filtering out the worst and selecting the best, time is the constantly moving
factor in this catalytic cracking. But alas! so much broken glass is given for
diamonds in SF that every true diamond must be dimmed, if any at all are to be
found in these mountains of waste. The worst eclipses the best; true, but this
is only the prima facie notion. In reality the perfection of a work of
art is only in its potentiality, its chance of maturing, of expanding in
meanings; and there are some necessary preconditions for this kind of growth:
the duration of contacts (between a work and its readers), the attention given
to each work, and so on. All this can be translated into the technical language
of information theory, with its "channel capacity," "noise-signal
ratio," etc. The most relevant piece of truth in information theory is the
rule that when we have too many signals, their common resultant can only be
noise. The principal factor in the killing of creation in our time is the law of
large numbers. The hyper-saturation of the market is a suicidal process in our
culture: the forces of selection are paralyzed. So what determines the success
of a literary work? To an ever greater degree, the determinants are accidental;
where there was once self-organization through maturation and discriminative
feedback, now there is only chance. If we have not yet reached the breaking
point, the point at which the randomization of "natural selection" inculture wipes out all other kinds of selection, we are surely moving, and
with acceleration, to this point of no return.
Let me point out some symptoms of this malaise in the artistic genre of SF.
Firstly, there is the staggering discrepancy between the literally cosmical
aspirations of SF and its realizations. The cosmos is already miniaturized to
pocketsize in a vast bulk of SF books. This miniaturization is counteracted only
by means of words: by adjectives, say, in statements that the distances between
the stars are "immensely great," by the notion of cosmonautics with
speeds measured in "kilolights," etc. But a pocketsize universe simply
cannot be taken seriously, so we have already a grotesque unintentionally
attained in this writing--a dangerous and bad omen.
Secondly, a growing number of books show signs of very strong referential
bonds with the whole background of science fiction. These books, when put in the
hands of a reader with no experience in SF, remain simply incomprehensible. They
look as if they had been mutilated, and truly they have been mutilated: such a
book is no closed system, no sovereign independent entity, no self-sustaining
organization of meanings but is instead a fragment, a particular and incidental
embodiment of the trend now fashionable in SF. In a word, these books have
already lost the central. attribute of a work of art: individual, nonrepetitive,
unique characteristics. They are very similar each to other, and even if they
differ, their differences are dominated by their general resemblance. This is
pulp in the primary, material sense of the word.
The disindividualizing trend can eventually become the dominant one in all
branches of art; then our present views will perish, as a transitory phase in
the evolution of culture. I do not forecast this state of affairs; I consider it
only a serious possibility. To claim today that one will spend years in the
writing of a novel--as Thomas Mann did, working ten or twelve years on a single
book--would be not a sign of spectacular courage but rather of madness. Who can
know what the fate of a book planned now would be twelve years from today? There
is building up a pressure that necessitates the synchronization of creative
plans and practical considerations (marketing) in a writer's production: he is
forced to write under conditions more and more resembling those in the typical
production of mass goods.
Perhaps all this is so, but what has it to do with Dr. Plank's essay, which
introduces into the relation of men and machines such notions as this of the
"Don Quixote effect"?
Firstly, one can put the notion "escapist" or "estranged
mind" for Dr. Plank's notion "Don Quixote," and
"empiricist" for "Sancho Panza." This would already be a
somewhat polemical substitution, since I have stated above that I understand a
literary work to be a union of these opposites. When you have estrangement only
for estrangement's sake, you are escaping the real world. The presence of both
Don Quixote and Sancho Panza in Cervantes' novel is no chance accident,
neither is the epilogue of this great book.
Secondly, we have in literary criticism the choice between the normative and
the descriptive approach. A normative approach must ,necessarily end with the
construction of a normative aesthetics. A normativistic critic is forced to
throw 98 or 99% of SF to the wolves, and to plead for a "better, future SF"--and so he himself becomes a utopian, since no man can by himself change a big
complex trend in the social or in the cultural life of his society. There is
simply no substitute for natural selection as a means of preserving prominent
works of art and drowning bad ones in oblivion. So even if I am biased here in
that I feel a strong attraction toward the normative attitude, I must also
sympathize with the descriptive study of literature, for I am a science addict,
and the egalitarian mode of research is typical of science.
Now descriptive research is not a univocal term, for we have both
synchronical and diachronical modes of description and generalization. The
synchronical mode was first worked out by the structuralist school: here the
central problem is how a given work has been put together and what its relations
are with the proper genological paradigm. The second school, more traditional,
treats a work as a link in the chain of sociocultural and philosophical events
distributed along the time axis of human history. The structuralist mode of
research is, alas, insufficient, since its theoretical apparatus has no
necessary resolving power: it cannot distinguish between certain subsets of
complex literary texts; e.g., between a dull (and boring) complexity and a
brilliant (and fascinating) one. (This is a matter of fact, not openly stated by
the structuralists themselves.)
The second school tends to explain away the immanent quality of every
literary work, since in this historical perspective a given work is only a point
of hybridization of some antecedent current.,; of thought: at the end of the
analysis the work in question is reduced to a handful of other works,
philosophical viewpoints, and sociological concepts.
Dr . Plank has taken another road, a third road: he has inverted the
canonical attitude of considering an artistic work as the
ultimate object of
study. The SF landscape is for him a projection of the deep currents
building up tensions in the base of human minds. He treats SF as an expression
of those forces., In The Emotional Significance of Imaginary Beings (1968)
he has stated that a bad, primitive SF story is more instructive than an SF
masterpiece, since in a primitive story the primary forces working at the base
of creation are not camouflaged by the author's, skills, by all the evasive
techniques of narration that are typical of the sophisticated and talented
writer (pp88-89). In this way Dr. Plank has shown most clearly his own critical
attitude, which is by no means a proper one for the "pure" critic of
literature.
His is rather the attitude of the scientist and physician, as will appear in
the following consideration. For the physician there are of course easy and
difficult cases, but there are no "good" or "bad" symptoms
of an illness. All symptoms have
the same value
as signs, and this also
applies for the psychologist or psychiatrist, since such a man does not evaluate
the enunciations of his patients in the way we would evaluate those same
enunciations in everyday life; for him the enunciations are not statements about
fact but rather symptoms of the patient's mental state. It is also true that a
taxonomist does not distinguish between "good" and "bad"
species: cockroaches and gazelles are equals to him, for his function does not
include the aesthetic (or moral) evaluation of what he is studying.
This scientistic attitude is alien to literary criticism, and if applied
systematically, it nullifies the axiological viewpoint. The analyzed work of art
ceases to be a work of
art in the proper sense, for it is no longer the
ultimate object of study, being used as an apparatus pointing out and magnifying
the basic pattern of the emotions active as factors of selection and creation in
the author-reader complex.
What survives as organism or species is neither "bad" nor
"good" in the eyes of the biologist. There are criteria of
"badness" and "goodness" at work in natural evolution, but
they are of a "technological" (i.e., pragmatical) character: what
survives is evidently "good" and what dies out evidently
"bad"--in the sense of "badly built"--and so unfit to
survive. Now when we substitute the salability of books for the survival fitness
of species, we have before us the proper model of the critical attitude proposed
by Dr. Plank. (The set of all readers stands here for the environment of
organisms.) Practically all SF is trash; nevertheless not all SF books are
selling equally well. Fandom prefers some books and rejects others. Why? Because
those others were badly written? No, rather because the privileged and selected
out are in tune with certain expectations of the readers. There is apparently a
unisonance involved in this process of filtering, a unisonance of all the
unconsciousnesses involved, those of the authors and of the readers.
But this is still an interesting mode of approach. It is worth pointing out
that Michel Butor has proposed that SF authors work together, in big
collectives, to build up a single fictitious world; this proposal caused some
indignation on the Olympian heights of SFWA.1 But no one has remarked
that Butor's idea is already accomplished to 80 or 90%, and this accomplishment
manifests itself in the syncytial character of all produced works that have in
common practically the same fictitious universe; that is, falsified in the same
way, with "hyperlight travel," with time loops, with parallel worlds,
with man-reduplicating machines, etc.
The sole weakness of Dr. Plank's approach is this: if for the sake of the
argument I accept his general assumptions and approve his attitude, I must still
disagree with many of his particular statements. But there is no point in
opening a polemic, in writing diatribes. What I could say would not in the least
change the principal object of disagreement. My arguments, on this level of
discourse, would have the same inbuilt weaknesses as those of Dr. Plank. On this
level there are simply no methods of proving who is right and who is wrong.
Here, in this psychoanalytical approach, we have no simple basal facts--no facts
already established beyond any reasonable doubt. Sam Lundwall has written that
we have in SF two kinds of artificial beings in accordance with an ambivalence
typical and well known in the domain of the unconscious. Androids are sexed but
robots are sexually disarmed, because we, the readers, are at one and the same
time attracted and repelled by the idea of sexual intimacy with an artificial
man or woman.2
Perhaps Lundwall is right, but how could we prove that he is? Breadth of
imagination cannot represent the highest instance of appeal in the theory of
literature (or of its genres). Of how to evaluate Dr. Plank's hypothesis on the
"Don Quixote effect" or "complex," I have no idea. After
reading "Quixote's Mills" I have the same feeling as after finishing The
Emotional Significance of Imaginary Beings, the feeling that both these
texts should start at the point where they come to an abrupt end. I can only
hope that this is not a dead end. Perhaps statistical analysis of a truly big
set of SF works could be of some help here. Their central leitmotives could be
analyzed in search of statistical significance. So we need now some computers,
some programs, some men with proper capabilities, and of course a lot of money.
This is how literary considerations are ending today.
Perhaps I should add some words explaining that I do not see any serious
disagreement between Dr. Plank's position and my own with respect to the
"blasphemous nature" of robots in our culture. In my essay on robots,
I did not claim that I was enumerating all the factors involved in "anti-robotical"
feelings and/or anxiety, but I thought that my argument was reasonable in the
form of a selective approximation of the problem. The problem is of course a
very complex one, and my essay was a minor thing, written for a limited
audience.3
NOTES
1 See Michel Butor, "Science Fiction: The Crisis of Its Growth,"
and James Blish, "On Science Fiction Criticism," in Thomas D. Clareson,
ed., SF. The Other Side of Realism (1971), ppl57-70.
2 Sam J. Lundwall, Science Fiction: What It's All About (Ace Books
1971), §7.
3 "Robots in Science Fiction," written in German for Quarber
Mercur, No. 21 (Nov. 1969); an English translation appears in Clareson
pp307-25.
ABSTRACT
Dr. Plank has inverted the canonical attitude of considering an
artistic work as the ultimate object of study. The SF landscape is for him a projection of
the deep currents building up tensions in the base of human minds. He reads SF as an
expression of those forces. In The Emotional Significance of Imaginary Beings (1968),
he stated that a bad, primitive SF story is more instructive than a SF masterpiece, since
in a primitive story the primary forces working at the base of creation are not
camouflaged by the authors skill. In this way, Dr. Plank has shown his own critical
attitude, which is by no means a proper one for the "pure" critic of literature.
His is rather the attitude of the physician and scientist. For the physician there are of
course easy and difficult cases, but there are no "good" or "bad"
symptoms of an illness. All symptoms have the same value as signs. It is also true that a
taxonomist does not distinguish between "good" and "bad" species:
cockroaches and gazelles are equals to him, for his function does not include the
aesthetic (or moral) evaluation of what he is studying. This "scientistic"
attitude is alien to literary criticism. The analyzed work of art ceases to be art in the
proper sense, for it is no longer the ultimate object of study. The sole weakness of Dr.
Planks psychological approach is this: even if I approve his attitude and
assumptions, I must still disagree with many of his particular statements. Of how to
evaluate Dr. Planks hypothesis on the "Don Quixote effect" I have no idea,
but after reading "Quixotes Mills" I have the feeling that the text should
start at the point where it comes to an abrupt end.
RESPONSE BY DR. PLANK
Responding in a spirit of magnanimity, Stanislaw Lem has widened the area of
conceptualization rather than that of argument. Any extended answer by me would
merely impair this desirable effect, so I'll be brief.
He is right, of course, that my basic approach is neither normative nor
descriptive--in fact, primarily one of psychological study rather than either
type of literary criticism. I may well be guilty of not having kept the three
approaches as separate as they ought to be.
I can't agree more than with Lem's judgment that my book would be better if
it went on (and it will hardly surprise anybody who knows publishing problems to
learn that the manuscript was thrice as long originally). I doubt that this
would necessarily take us as far as to computers. The science and art of
sampling has developed sufficiently, I hope to spare us such a step that I, for
one, still feel, without blushing, to be bit "unheimlich."
Back
to
Home