# 6 = Volume 2, Part 2 = July 1975
Aija Ozolins
Dreams and Doctrines: Dual Strands in
Frankenstein
In her Journal the entry made by Mary Shelley for February 22, 1815,
records the birth of a seven-month baby that was "not expected to
live." The laconic entry for March 6, "Find my baby dead,"
understates the impact of the child's death, as is indicated by the entry for
March 9: "Still think about my little baby—'tis hard indeed for a mother
to lose a child." How deeply Mary brooded on her loss is apparent from the
entry for March 19: "Dream that my little baby came to life again; that it
had only been cold, and that we rubbed it before the fire and it lived. Awake
and find no baby."1 This dream of reanimation apparently lodged
in Mary's subconscious and eventually blended with the more famous dream of the
following year, the one described in the Introduction to the 1831 edition of Frankenstein:
"I saw—with shut eyes, but acute mental vision,—I saw the pale student
of unhallowed arts kneeling beside the thing he had put together. I saw the
hideous phantasm of a man stretched out, and then, on the working of some
powerful engine, show signs of life, and stir with an uneasy, half vital
motion."2
Having thus found "her story" in a dream, Mary began her
contribution to that famous set of ghost stories with what is now the opening of
§5—"It was on a dreary night of November"—and with the intention
of writing only "a short tale." But Shelley urged her to develop the
idea at greater length, which she did, by rationalizing and moralizing the
spontaneous core of horror.
This twofold process of composition—subconscious generation and conscious
elaboration—has resulted in an obviously layered work: e.g., the monster's
narrative is embedded in Frankenstein's narrative, which in turn is framed by
Walton's Letters and Continuation. Knowing that §5 was part of the original
kernel, critics have reached divergent conclusions on the subsequent accretions:
some hold the Gothic core of the dream as central and object to the didacticism
of the monster's narrative, while others approve of the social and moral themes
and thus regard the monster's narrative as central.3 I propose to
examine both the oneiric and the didactic components, beginning with a survey of
the dreams that figure in the novel and a discussion of the doppelgÄnger motif,
continuing with the didactic component as expressed in the monster's narrative,
and concluding with the didacticism of the Frankenstein and Walton narratives.
1. THE MONSTER AS DOPPELGÄNGER. The word dream is used in the novel
in various senses. It can be a synonym for the ideals of Frankenstein and
Walton, who both refer to their lonely quests as dreams or daydreams (§§ 01,
02, 3, 4, 5). It can also signify what is illusory or insubstantial: before the
creation of the monster, and especially afterward, Frankenstein often speaks of
how unreal his life seems (§§ 3, 7, 17, 21). Finally, there are actual dreams:
Frankenstein has a premonitory dream of his fiancée's death (§5); he has
nightmares after the monster has killed Henry Clerval (§21); and sometimes he
finds solace in dreams in which he is united with all his loved ones
(§§23-24). In most instances dreams are associated with illusoriness or with
ideals that turn into nightmares of horror and guilt, but at the same time they
all indirectly point back to Mary's seminal dream.
Let us return to that original dream to examine another element that informs
the novel—the motif of the doppelgÄnger. Whatever we call it—shadow,
objectified id, or double of the ego personality4—this motif of a
second self constitutes the chief source of the novel's latent power.
Occasionally the double in literature is an embodiment of good (as in Poe's
"William Wilson"), but more often he is an image of man's innate
propensity toward evil.
There is ample evidence in the novel that the creature functions as the
scientist's baser self. Frankenstein's epithets for him consistently connote
evil: devil, fiend, daemon, horror, wretch, monster, monstrous image, vile
insect, abhorred entity, detested form, hideous phantasm, odious companion,
and demoniacal corpse. Neutral terms like creature and being
are comparatively rare. Most important, there is Frankenstein's thinking of him
as "my own vampire, my own spirit let loose from the grave, and forced to
destroy all that was dear to me" (§7). And after each murder Frankenstein
acknowledges his complicity: "I not in deed, but in effect, was the true
murderer" (§9); cf §§ 8, 21, 22).
One sure sign of the double is his haunting presence. Maria Mahoney
characterizes the feeling as "someone or something behind you, an ominous
adversary dogging your footsteps...[a] sinister and truly evil figure lurking in
the dark."5 Even though Frankenstein initially flees from his
creature and even though their direct confrontations are few, the monster is
nevertheless a ubiquitous presence in his life. Wandering about the city in
order to evade his creature, Frankenstein compares himself to Coleridge's
Mariner, who also walks "in fear and dread,/...Because he knows a frightful
fiend/Doth close behind him tread" (§5). When he agrees to fashion a mate
for his creature he is told to expect constant surveillance: "I shall watch
your progress with unutterable anxiety; and fear not but that when you are ready
I shall appear" (§17). After breaking his promise he is even more
oppressed by a sense of the monster's presence; even his days take on a
nightmarish quality: "although the sun shone," he felt only "a
dense and frightful darkness, penetrated by no light but the glimmer of two eyes
that glared" at him (§21).
The psychological motif of the double is reinforced by several visual
tableaux that hint at a secret sympathy between the monster and his maker. At
the beginning of her dream Mary saw "the pale student of unhallowed arts
kneeling beside the thing he had put together," but at its conclusion the
positions are reversed, with the "horrid thing" standing at the
student's bedside and "looking on him with yellow, watery, but speculative
eyes" (§I). This picture is repeated at the end of the novel when the
monster stands sorrowfully over the corpse of Frankenstein (§C). Similarly,
there are three moonlight encounters between the two. Although meetings by
lightning and moonlight are a conventional part of the Gothic landscape, Mary's
conjunction of man, moon, and monster is traceable to her dream and serves to
emphasize the close relationship between them. Also, because most of these
moonlight encounters are preceded by a crime, they spotlight the creature's
jeering, malevolent form.
The last and most important point regarding the double is the necessity to
confront and recognize the dark aspect of one's personality in order to
transform it by an act of conscious choice. Ideally, the Shadow diminishes as
one's awareness increases. "Freedom comes," according to Mahoney,
"not in eliminating the Shadow...but in recognizing him in yourself."6
Prospero acknowledges Caliban—"This thing of darkness I acknowledge
mine"—but Frankenstein's typical reactions are first to flee, then to
kill. His rejection of his creature is crucial, both in the present
psychological context and in the sociological context we shall consider later.
Frankenstein, as Philmus says, is always "fleeing from self-knowledge,"
always seeking "to lose himself in the external world."7
and thus denying, in Nelson's words, the "nether forces for which he should
have accepted a fully aware responsibility."8
2. THE DEFENSE OF POLYPHEMUS. The duality of the novel's didactic component
is foreshadowed in the juxtaposition of the subtitle referring to Frankenstein,
"The Modern Prometheus," and the epigraph from Paradise Lost,
which applies to the creature's predicament: "Did I request thee, Maker,
from my clay/To mould me man? Did I solicit thee/From darkness to promote
me?" In Frankenstein's narrative the creature constructed from parts of
cadavers and vivified by electricity is an "artificial man," but when
Mary traces the social implications of the experiment, when she humanizes the
monster and elicits sympathy for him, and when she allows him to tell his own
story, summarizing his life from his first day of consciousness to his encounter
with Frankenstein many months later, he takes on the aspect of the "natural
man" who recapitulates the stages between man in the state of nature and
man in civilized society. As such, he is often the mouthpiece for Lockean,
Godwinian, and Shelleyan ideas.9
In the six chapters told from the creature's point of view we learn how he
acquired knowledge and benevolence and why he became malevolent. The agents of
his education were his sensations, his observations of the De Lacey family, and
his reading. Faithful to the Lockean concept that there are no innate ideas, all
knowledge being derived from experience, the creature's monologue begins with
the Lockean progression from inarticulate feelings and indistinct perceptions to
conceptualized emotions and ideas:
It is with considerable difficulty that I
remember the original era of my being: all the events of that period appear
confused and indistinct. A strange multiplicity of sensations seized me, and
I saw, felt, heard, and smelt, at the same time; and it was, indeed, a long
time before I learned to distinguish between the operations of my various
senses.... No distinct ideas occupied my mind; all was confused. I felt
light, and hunger, and thirst, and darkness.... [after about a week] I began
to distinguish my sensations from each other.... [About a month later] my
sensations had...become distinct, and my mind received every day additional
ideas. (§11)
The De Lacey family, a society in miniature,
is the creature's school for studying human language and human nature: from
"my beloved cottagers.... I learned to admire their virtues, and to
deprecate the vices of mankind," for "benevolence and generosity were
ever present before me, inciting within me a desire to become an actor in the
busy scene where so many admirable qualities were called forth and
displayed" (§15). When he realizes that stealing food from them increases
their distress, he satisfies himself with nuts, roots, and berries; moreover, he
succeeds in lightening their toil by secretly supplying them with firewood:
"I observed with pleasure that he [Felix] did not go to the forest that
day, but spent it in repairing the cottage and cultivating the garden"
(§12). The creature has by now ascended high on the Godwinian scale of
pleasure: at first he took delight in birdsong and moonlight, then in learning,
and finally in sympathy with others—all in accord with Godwin's belief that
the pleasures of "intellectual feeling...sympathy, and self-approbation"
are nobler than the pleasures of the senses.10
The scope of the creature's education is
broadened by reading: Werther stirs his private feelings, awakening
"despondency and gloom"; Plutarch extends his thoughts to "new
and mighty scenes of action" in the realms of public affairs; and portions
of Paradise Lost reflect his own outcast state (§15). Volney's Ruins,
"a widely read compendium of meditations on history...strongly coloured by
the author's radical and deist views,"11 evokes a mixed reaction
which is at the same time an oblique Godwinian criticism of society: "Was
man, indeed, at once so powerful, so virtuous, and magnificent, yet so vicious
and base?... For a long time I could not conceive how one man could go forth to
murder his fellow, or even why there were laws and governments; but when I heard
details of vice and bloodshed, my wonder ceased, and I turned away with disgust
and loathing" (§13).
The course of the creature's education brings
out another Godwinian concept central to the novel: "the actions and
dispositions of mankind are the offspring of circumstances and events, and not
of any original determination that they bring into the world."12
Although some of the Romantics ascribe innate goodness to natural man, Mary
follows her father in stressing the formative influence of "circumstances
and events." For example, the creature suggests that whereas Plutarch
aroused and strengthened his desire for good, a less edifying volume might have
had a different effect:
I felt the greatest ardour for virtue rise
within me, and abhorrence for vice, as far as I understood the significance
of those terms.... Induced by these feelings, I was of course led to admire
peaceful lawgivers, Numa, Solon, and Lycurgus, in preference to Romulus and
Theseus. The patriarchal lives of my protectors caused these impressions to
take a firm hold on my mind; perhaps, if my first introduction to humanity
had been made by a young soldier, burning for glory and slaughter, I should
have been imbued with different sensations. (§15)when the
creature suffers social rejection: "I was benevolent and good; misery made
me a fiend. Make me happy and I shall again be virtuous" (§10); "I
cannot believe that I am the same creature whose thoughts were once filled with
sublime and transcendent visions of the beauty and majesty of goodness. But it
is even so; the fallen angel becomes the malignant devil" (§C).
In the series of rejections that causes this
demonic transformation (Frankenstein's flight at the moment of the creature's
awakening, Felix's driving him from the door of the cottage, the attempt on his
life by the rustic whose child he has saved from drowning), in the series of
crimes with which the creature responds to his rejection, and in the creature's
demand that Frankenstein create a female to be his mate ("My vices are the
children of a forced solitude that I abhor; and my virtues will necessarily
arise when I live in communion with an equal" [§17]), Mary follows her
father and her husband in insisting on the causal connection between social
acceptance and virtue, between social rejection and crime.13 The
failure of some modern scholars to recognize this connection has led them to
recast the creature as a Noble Outlaw, a champion of violence and rebellion,14
but such an interpretation is surely inconsistent with the creature's own
attitude toward his deeds: "Polluted by crimes, and torn with the bitterest
remorse, where can I find rest but in death?" (§C).
One final piece of extra-textual evidence that
indicates how Mary intended her creature to be viewed has been generally
overlooked. To a remark in a letter from Leigh Hunt, "Polyphemus...always
appears to me a pathetic rather than a monstrous person, though his disappointed
sympathies at last made him cruel,"15 Mary replied (April 6,
1819), "I have written a book in defence of Polypheme have I not?"16
The reference must be to the story of Polyphemus and Galatea as told in §12 of
Ovid's Metamorphoses. In 1815, day by day with scarcely a break from
April 8 to May 13, Mary had diligently applied herself to the translation of
Ovid's fables. Consider the parallels between the predicaments of Frankenstein's
creature and the giant, uncouth, one-eyed Polyphemus, who falls in love with a
beautiful nymph. Disdained by Galatea, the Cyclops composes a lovelorn song:
"But didst thou know me well, thou wouldest repine to have fled...."17
This plaint is echoed in the Monster's words to Walton: "Once I falsely
hoped to meet with beings, who, pardoning my outward form, would love me for the
excellent qualities which I was capable of unfolding" (§C). Preferring the
handsome Acis, Galatea spurns the suit of
Polyphemus, who, having one day seen them in each other's arms, tosses a ton of
rocks at Acis and thus buries him. When we recall the monster's chagrin that
"the gentle words of Agatha, and the animated smiles of the charming
Arabian were not for [him]," his envy upon seeing the sleeping Justine
("Here...is one of those whose joy-imparting smiles are bestowed on all but
me"), and, above all, his bitterness when Frankenstein and Elizabeth sought
"enjoyment in feelings and passions from the indulgence of which [he] was
for ever barred" (§§ 13, 16, 24), we can understand why Mary Shelley
spoke of her book as a "defence of Polypheme."
3. THE DEFENSE OF THE MODERN PROMETHEUS. A
created being has certain rights and needs—hence Mary Shelley's defense of her
Polyphemus. But the morality of Frankenstein's endeavor is more open to
question, as is that of Walton's search for a northern passage and of scientific
research in general. I find that, on the whole, Mary sanctions Frankenstein's
and Walton's Promethean quests, but does so with vacillations and with a
particular view of morality in mind. The fact that these scientific endeavors
are alternately presented as culpable and laudable may stem from Mary's
intensely dualistic temperament: "I see things pretty clearly, but cannot
demonstrate them. Besides, I feel the counter-arguments too strongly.... besides
that, on some topics...I am far from making up my own mind.... I may distrust my
own judgment too much—be too indolent and too timid."18
It is perilous to assume that with respect to
morality Mary was writing within an orthodox Christian framework. Her childhood
had been spent in an atmosphere of determinism, and she was widely read in
Godwin, Voltaire, Rousseau, Halbach, Volney, and other deistic or materialistic philosophes
of the Enlightenment, whose spirit pervades Frankenstein so thoroughly
that Aldiss terms it a "dark and atheistic work."19 Godwin
rejected "Love thy neighbor as thyself," for he doubted that a man and
his neighbor were likely to be of equal worth, and instead measured a person's
moral worth by his contribution to the general good. Thus he was able to declare
morality an exact science concerned with "nothing else but a calculation of
consequences."20 Although Mary at times shows an insight into
the non-quantifiable essence of morality, she generally agrees with Godwin that
virtue is a contribution to the general welfare and that vice is an infraction
of the social law. The quests of Frankenstein and Walton, therefore, should be
judged in terms of their intended and actual effects. Mary is at pains to stress
the humanitarian motives of both men. Frankenstein seeks the elixir of life in
order to "banish disease from the human frame, and render man invulnerable
to any but a violent death" (§2), while Walton dreams of conferring
"inestimable benefit...on all mankind to the last generation, by
discovering a passage near the pole...or by ascertaining the secret of the
magnet" (§01).
With Mary's dualistic temperament and moral
biases in mind, let us examine her attitudes toward these scientific projects.
At first she appears to be pointing an explicit moral against presumption.
Frankenstein recounts his tale to Walton as an exemplum to dissuade the latter
from continuing his Arctic expedition:
"Unhappy man! Do you share my
madness? Have you drank also of the intoxicating draught? Hear me, let me
reveal my tale, and you will dash the cup from your lips!... You seek for
knowledge and wisdom, as I once did.... When I reflect that you are pursuing
the same course, exposing yourself to the same dangers which have rendered
me what I am, I imagine that you may deduce an apt moral from my
tale...." (§04)
"Learn from me, if not by my
precepts, at least by my example, how dangerous is the acquirement of
knowledge, and how much happier that man is who believes his native town to
be the world, than he who aspires to become greater than his nature will
allow." (§4)
Through statements such as these Mary is
clearly endorsing the traditional taboo against seeking forbidden knowledge but
with the important qualification that the search for knowledge is dangerous and
unlawful only if it impairs the social affections:
A human being in perfection ought always
to preserve a calm and peaceful mind, and never allow passion or transitory
desire to disturb his tranquillity. I do not think that the pursuit of
knowledge is an exception to this rule. If the study to which you apply
yourself has a tendency to weaken your affections, and to destroy your taste
for...simple pleasures...then that study is certainly unlawful. (§4)
Although Walton is usually assumed to be as
guilty as Frankenstein of sacrificing human ties for knowledge, he seems to me
less culpable. After all, he writes home regularly to his sister, he expresses
great longing for a friend, and he shows concern for the welfare of his crew,
even to the point of yielding to their entreaties to abandon the enterprise.
Nevertheless the alienating connotations of ice and snow, of sailing farther and
farther away from human habitation, do tacitly impugn the morality of his
mission.21
This emphasis on human feelings is traceable
to the writings of Godwin and his disciple Shelley. Godwin is commonly
associated with the stern rationalism of the first edition of Political
Justice (1793), but the subsequent editions of this work (1796, 1798) along
with his novels show a revaluation of the importance of feeling, largely because
of his own brief, happy marriage to Mary Wollstonecraft. Thus he argues that
"Even knowledge, and the enlargement of the intellect, are poor, when
unmixed with sentiments of benevolence and sympathy," and that the exercise
of "domestic and private affections" is a prerequisite for effectively
displaying benevolence in society at large.22 This humanistic ethic,
as Goldberg points out, is quite prevalent among Mary's contemporaries, notably
Shelley, Byron, and Paine: in their hierarchy of values love or sympathy is a
higher good than abstract knowledge, and their criterion for establishing this
priority is human, not divine.23
The lesson of Frankenstein's tale to Walton is
thus that man should avoid temptation of knowledge lest it lead to estrangement
from family and society, but it turns out that after implanting this idea so
firmly in our minds, Mary Shelley has Frankenstein completely reverse himself—a
crucial point that scholars have generally overlooked—in his exhortation to
Walton's mutinous crew:
"You were hereafter to be hailed as
the benefactors of your species.... And now, behold, with the first...mighty
and terrific trial of your courage, you shrink away...; ye need not have
come thus far, and dragged your captain to shame and defeat, merely to prove
yourselves cowards. Oh! be men, or be more than men.... Do not return to
your families with the stigma of disgrace marked on your brows. Return, as
heroes who have fought and conquered." (§C)
The sudden bravado of this speech is soon
negated by Frankenstein's dying words—"Farewell, Walton! Seek happiness
in tranquility, and avoid ambition, even if it be the apparently innocent one of
distinguishing yourself in science and discoveries"—and then partly
reconfirmed!: I have myself been blasted in these hopes, yet another may
succeed."
What are we, to make of these divergent
pronouncements? Are they intended to reflect Frankenstein's confused state of
mind as he nears death, or do they mirror the author's indecisiveness?
The same ambiguity of conception afflicts
Frankenstein's role as "the modern Prometheus." On the one hand, some
of his utterances imply guilt for overstepping human limitations: he feels as if
his "soul were grappling with a palpable enemy" (§3); he calls
himself the "living monument of presumption and rash ignorance" (§7);
he grieves over the work of his "thrice-accursed hands" as he beholds
the graves of William and Justine, "the first hapless victims of [his]
unhallowed arts" (§8); he shudders at "the mad enthusiasm that
hurried [him] on to the creation of [his] hideous enemy" (§21); and he
regards the making of the second creature as an "unearthly occupation"
(§18). On the other hand, these expressions of mea culpa seem merely
perfunctory against the novel's general cast of scientific naturalism:
Frankenstein speaks of "the mechanism of my being" (§3); he considers
man a complex and wonderful animal (§4); and Mary's Introduction contains an
obviously deistic phrase: "the stupendous mechanism of the Creator of the
world."24 Thus it seems that Mary Shelley on the whole defends
her "modern Prometheus." If the consequences of his experiment were
disastrous, his goal of discovering "the secrets of heaven and earth"
was nonetheless legitimate for a man of science.
Although scholars tend to assume that Mary
shares Byron's and Shelley's conception of Prometheus as the adversary of love,
the benefactor and suffering champion of mankind,25 I believe that
she focuses on the often overlooked role of Prometheus as the maker of natural
man and hence a prototype for any maker of artificial man. In classical
mythology this Titan is a deeply enigmatic figure, acting both as lawful creator
and as usurper of divine prerogative. To the Greeks, notably Aeschylus, he was
Prometheus pyrphoros, the fire-bringer; to the Romans, however, he was
Prometheus plasticator, the creator of man; by the second or third
century the two roles were fused, "so that the fire stolen by Prometheus
was also the fire of life with which he animated his man of clay."26
Although Frankenstein's animation of an
artificial being is sufficient to account for his epithet "the modern
Prometheus," there is a highly probable source for the phrase itself. I
agree with Mario Praz, who suggests that Frankenstein may be an answer to La
Mettrie's call for "un nouveau Prométhée." Praz believes that
"the similarity of the Frankenstein theme to the attempts made in
France to create an artificial man may not be due to mere coincidence," and
such scholars as Cohen, Ebeling, and Swoboda, less cautious than Praz, emphasize
the work of 17th-century horologists and mechanists as precedents for
Frankenstein's project.27 The makers of automata and experimenters in
spontaneous generation saw themselves as gaining legitimate control over nature
rather than impiously delving into the mysteries of God. Their experiments,
which indicated that the causes of all organic and inorganic developments were
to be sought within nature, not in God or chance, were immensely important to
the 18th-century materialist philosophes. In 1740 Abraham Trembley
discovered that when a certain kind of fresh-water polyp is cut into pieces,
each piece becomes a new polyp. Julien Offray de La Mettrie used the self -regenerative
property of the polyp to support his doctrine of materialism: if an animal's
soul or vital principle is divisible with its body, then the same might be true
of the human soul—i.e., man has no soul apart from his material organization.
After rejecting "immateriality" or "spirituality" as a final
cause, La Mettrie postulated that "matter possesses intrinsically the
causes of its activity and organization."28
Le Mettrie's materialist ideas culminate in Man
a Machine (i.e., L'Homme machine, 1748):
[Man] is to the ape, and to the most
intelligent animals, as the planetary pendulum of Huyghens is to a watch of
Julien Leory. More instruments, more wheels and more springs were necessary
to mark the movements of the planets than to mark or strike the hours; and
Vaucanson, who needed more skill for making his flute player than for making
his duck, would have needed still more to make a talking man, a mechanism no
longer to be regarded as impossible, especially in the hands of another
Prometheus [d'un nouveau Prométhée].29
La Mettrie has singled out the leading
mechanists. The French watchmaker Julien Leory excelled in the construction of
large clocks and pendulums. In the application of mechanical laws he was
superseded by Huyghens, the Dutch mathematician, physicist, and astronomer
renowned for improving the telescope, developing the wave theory of light, and
inventing a pendulum clock which was a miniature model of the solar system,
measuring the movements of the planets. Yet he was eclipsed by the ingenuity and
skill of Vaucanson, whose three celebrated automata—a flute player, a drummer,
and a digesting duck—were shown throughout Europe and (in 1742) in London.30
The duck was a three-dimensional working model of the functions of eating,
drinking, digesting, and swimming, with the internal mechanisms fully exposed to
view. The wooden flutist played twelve melodies while moving the fingers, lips,
and tongue. Vaucanson was as meticulous with the flute as with the flutist: he
made 300 flutes before he was satisfied with the tonal quality. He even
"cherished a secret ambition to make an artificial man. At the instigation
of Lous XV he did indeed attempt to make a model with heart, veins, and
arteries, but he died before completing his task."31
Frankenstein's defiant, pro-science stance at
the end of the novel is directly in line with the experimental outlook exhibited
by the alchemists, the 17th-century mechanists and horologists, the 18th-century
biologists, and most modern behavioral scientists and futurists. This is
undoubtedly one reason why the novel has remained popular to this day. Though
with part of her mind Mary Shelley may have endorsed Frankenstein's warning
against libido sciendi, she felt the claims of the opposite viewpoint
strongly enough to reverse the moral at the end and, more subtly, to permeate
the entire book with materialistic and mechanistic assumptions.
Frankenstein ,
as we have seen, is a markedly dualistic work, full of contrasts, conflicts, and
even contradictions. Mary's hero vacillates between rejection and advocacy of
modern Prometheanism in science. His creature is equally protean as he acts out
his various roles of horrific monster, evil alter ego, and pitiful Polyphemus. I
surmise that what makes Frankenstein so enduringly interesting is
precisely the tension between the claims of reason and imagination that it
exhibits. To borrow William Madden's comment on Chaucer, Mary Shelley's first
novel is instinct with that duality which lies at the very heart of life.
NOTES
1. Frederick L. Jones, ed., Mary Shelley's
Journal (1947).
2. The text followed here is that of Mary W.
Shelley, Frankenstein; Or, The Modern Prometheus, edited with an
Introduction by M.K. Joseph (1969). References are to chapter, with the
"Letters" cited as §01, §02, etc., "Walton's Continuation"
as §C, and the 1831 Introduction as §I.
3. The following scholars regard the dream-derived
narrative as central and thus deprecate amplification: Ernest A. Baker, The
History of the English Novel (1934), 5:217-19; Edith Birkhead, The Tale
of Terror: A Study of the Gothic Romance (1921), pp 161, 164; Milton
Millhauser, "The Noble Savage in Mary Shelley's 'Frankenstein'," Notes
and Queries 191(1946):248-50; D.J. Palmer and R.E. Dowse,
"'Frankenstein': A Moral Fable," The Listener 68(1962):284. The
following approve of amplifying the dream-vision
with social and moral themes: Harold Bloom, "Afterward," in Frankenstein
(Signet 1965), pp 219, 221; M.A. Goldberg, "Moral and Myth in Mrs.
Shelley's Frankenstein," Keats-Shelley Journal 8(1959):27-29.
4. The following studies of the double are
useful: Albert J. Guérard, "Concepts of the Double," in Stories of
the Double (1967); Carl F. Keppler, The Literature of the Second Self
(1972); Masao Myoshi, The Divided Self (1969); Robert Rogers, The
Double in Literature (1969); Ralph Tymms, Doubles in Literary Psychology
(1949).
5. Maria F. Mahoney, The Meaning in Dreams
and Dreaming: The Jungian Viewpoint (1966), p109.
6. Ibid., pp 108, 110, 114.
7. Robert M. Philmus, Into the Unknown: The
Evolution of Science Fiction from Francis Godwin to H.G. Wells (1970), p88.
8. Lowry Nelson, Jr., "Night Thoughts on
the Gothic Novel," Yale Review 52(1963): 247-48.
9. For Mary's reading before and during the
period of the composition of Frankenstein, see the Journal (Note
1); see also Katherine Richardson Powers, "The Influence of William Godwin
on the Novels of Mary Shelley" (University of Tennessee Dissertation 1972).
10. William Godwin, Enquiry Concerning
Political Justice and Its Influence on Morals and Happiness, ed. F.E.L.
Priestley (1946), 1:xxiii, 3:15.
11. Joseph (Note 2), p239, C.F. Volney, The
Ruins; Or, Meditations on the Revolutions of Empires, to which is Added the Law
of Nature (1857; first English edition, 1795).
12. Godwin (Note 10), 1:26.
13. Compare Goldberg (Note 3), pp33-35.
14. See the following: Stephen Crafts, "Frankenstein:
Camp Curiosity or Premonition?" Catalyst 3(1967):96-103; Milton A.
Mays, "Frankenstein: Mary Shelley's Black Theodicy," Southern
Humanities Review 3(1969):146-53; John L. McKenney, "Nietzsche and the
Frankenstein Creature," Dalhousie Review 41(1961):40-48. Peter
Thorslev's study, The Byronic Hero: Types and Prototypes (1962), pp 65-70,
contains a valuable discussion of how the Gothic villain of the 18th century
emerged as the Noble Outlaw of the 19th.
15. Elizabeth Nitchie, Mary Shelley: Author
of Frankenstein (1953), p17; also James Rieger, The Mutiny Within: The
Heresies of Percy Bysshe Shelley (1967), p247.
16. Frederick L. Jones, ed., The Letters of
Mary W. Shelley (1944), 1:66.
17. Ovid's Metamorphoses, Translated into
English Prose by Joseph Davidson (1797), p472.
18. Journal (Note 1), pp204-05.
19. Brian W. Aldiss, Billion Year Spree:
The True History of Science Fiction (US 1973), p199.
20. Godwin (Note 10), 1:126-29, 1:342, 3:17.
Volney (Note 11) expresses a similar concept in his Preface to The Ruins.
21. For the novel's symbolic geography see
William Walling, Mary Shelley (1972), pp 36-37, and Rieger (Note 15), pp
81-89. Rieger compares Frankenstein's exhortation to Ulysses' speech to his crew
in §26 of Dante's Inferno, the implication being that both are evil
counselors.
22. Godwin (Note 10), 1:311; Godwin's Preface
to St. Leon (1799) and to Fleetwood (1805).
23. Goldberg (Note 3), p33.
24. Mary Shelley's second work of fantasy, The
Last Man (1826), contains the following mechanistic references to man and
the world: "shattered mechanism," "earthly mechanism,"
"animal mechanism," "animal machine," "automation of
flesh," "mortal mechanism," "wheels and springs of
life," "mechanism of senses," and "the universal
machine."
25. Scholars who stress the rebellious nature
of Prometheus include Bloom, Goldberg, Palmer, and Dowse.
26. Joseph (Note 2), p. viii.>
27. Mario Praz, "Introductory Essay"
in Three Gothic Novels, ed. Peter Fairclough (Penguin Books 1968), p30;
John Cohen, Human Robots in Myth and Science (1961), pp 61, 68-88;
Hermann Ebeling, "Hachwort," in Frankenstein: oder der neue
Prometheus (Munich 1970), pp325-26; Helmut Swoboda, Der künstliche
Mensch (Munich 1967), pp 12, 87-98, 220-22.
28. Aram Vartanian, "Trembley's Polyp, La
Mettrie, and Eighteenth-Century French Materialism," Journal of the
History of Ideas 11(1950):271. My discussion is based on this article, which
covers pp 259-86.
29. Julian Offray de la Mettrie, Man a
Machine (1912), pp 70, 140-41. Also see Aram Vartanian, La Mettrie's
L'Homme machine: A Study in the Origins of an Idea (1960).
30. Ibid., pp 202-03; Praz (Note 27), p28.
Mary Shelley, in her Rambles in Germany and Italy (1844), 1:49, mentions
seeing a "self-acting" musical instrument at Lenzkirch.
31. Cohen (Note 27), pp 86-88; Swoboda (Note
27), p93.
ABSTRACT
Mary Shelleys Journal entry for February 22,
1815, records the birth of a seven-month baby that was "not expected to live":
she adds the entry "Find my baby dead" on 6 March. How deeply Mary brooded upon
her loss is apparent from the entry for March 19: "Dream that my little baby came to
life again, that it had only been cold, and that we rubbed it before the fire and it
lived. Awake and find no baby." This dream of reanimation evidently blended with the
more famous dream of the following year, the one described in the Introduction to the 1831
edition of Frankenstein: "I saw the hideous phantasm of a man stretched out
and then, on the working of some powerful engine, show signs of life, and stir with an
uneasy, half-vital motion." Having found "her story" in a dream, Mary
Shelley began her contribution to that famous set of ghost stories. The twofold process of
composition—subconscious generation and conscious elaboration—resulted in a
layered work: the monsters narrative is embedded in Frankensteins, which is in
term framed by Waltons letters and continuation. I examine Shelleys oneiric
and didactic components, beginning with a survey of the dreams that figure in the novel
and concluding with the didacticism of the Frankenstein and Walton narratives. Frankenstein
is a markedly dualistic work, full of contrasts, conflicts, and even contradictions.
Victor Frankenstein vacillates between rejection and advocacy of modern Prometheanism in
science, and his creature is equally protean as he acts out his various roles of horrific
monster, evil alter ego, and pitiful Polyphemus.
Back
to Home