#92 = Volume 31, Part 1 =
March 2004
Istvan Csicsery-Ronay, Jr.
Who Framed Science Fiction?
Peter Stockwell. The
Poetics of Science Fiction. Harlow, UK:
Longman, 2000. xi+250 pp. $80.00 hc; $25.20 pbk.
First published in 2000, Peter Stockwell’s The Poetics of Science Fiction
remains the most interesting book-length discussion of linguistics and sf since
Walter E. Meyers’s Aliens and Linguists (1980). That’s not actually
saying much, since very little work on the subject has appeared since then. More
relevant is that Stockwell’s book is also the first sustained attempt to go
beyond the two dominant models of a poetics of sf—Samuel R. Delany’s notion of
sf’s reading protocols and Darko Suvin’s notion of cognitive estrangement.
Meyers’s book is still useful and entertaining, but it is somewhat
old-fashioned and anchored in the genteel philological tradition concerned with
the evolution of language. For Meyers, actually existing sf is a museum of folly
about the real language. The genre has unique potential to show how language
might behave under the changed conditions of the future, on other worlds, or in
alien minds; but most sf writers, in Meyers’s view, depict alien and future
languages with much less knowledge and concern than they do the physics and
biologies of their imaginary worlds. Nothing marks Meyers’s nostalgia for the
philological better than his plea to regard The Lord of the Rings
(1954-55) as a work of sf because of Tolkien’s construction of the Elvish tongue
on principles as rigorously faithful to evolutionary linguistics as Hal Clement
was to physics in Mission of Gravity (1953). In the age of the Klingon
Language Institute, we need to cast the net wider.
Stockwell begins from very different premises. Instead of measuring how
adequate sf is to historical linguistics, he uses sf to illuminate how readers
of fiction convert linguistic cues into fictive contexts. Like Meyers, he
intends his book to do double-duty, using linguistics to explain the way sf is
read, and sf to theorize a poetics of reading. He works, for the most part,
within the theoretical framework of cognitive rhetoric most closely associated
with the work of Robin Lakoff and Mark Turner. Cognitive poetics, by extension,
must be concerned the relationship between human mental operations and the basic
operations of literary language. Stockwell is not all that clear about this. His
closest approximation to a definition is that poetics is “the linguistic and
cognitive organization of the genre” (3). I’m not sure exactly what this means;
I assume he means it is a practice, in which imagination, reflection and social
conventions reveal their inextricable connections. One thing it clearly does not
include in Stockwell’s formulation is the notion of an artist, or, for that
matter, a critic.
Stockwell starts out with something of a polemic:
A scientific poetics of literature, informed by modern linguistics, can do
everything that literary criticism can do, with the advantage that it is
rigorously analytical, differentiates between interpretations and reflecting
on them, and it is open to informed debate. Only some literary criticism is
able to do this.... (3)
Far from being a mechanical application of technical concepts, this sort of
linguistic analysis is, Stockwell claims, a far more flexible discipline than
technically ungrounded interpretation.
The same piece of science fiction can look quite different depending on
which level of analysis is applied to it. This is because a thorough poetics
is not about accounting for the text on its own and fixing a description of
it; it is about finding and exercising fruitful ways of understanding how
science fiction works as a reading experience. Literary linguistics is not
dissection; it is yoga.... (3)
Perhaps this means that, like a yoga, a scientific poetics uses specific
postures as a way to make reveal and cultivate the intimate connections between
the textual body and the organized consciousness.
For Stockwell, sf is uniquely suited for cognitive analysis because its
characteristic language puts a premium on plausibility, while continually
referring to unreal referents. At the level of words and sentences, readers
construct contextual frames that resemble their familiar experience of reality.
This inertial tendency to expend the least cognitive effort (i.e., to treat all
reference as if it were to reality) is constantly roused by information that
does not fit into familiar frames. Linguists speak of a class of words, called
deictic terms, that serve to anchor readers within a given frame of reference.
Stockwell argues that the commonly held notions of deixis need to be modified,
since they are based on the realistic assumption that words in fiction act the
way they do in everyday discourse. In sf, these anchoring terms refer again and
again to objects, temporal, and spatial domains, agents, etc. that are markedly
different from those of real experience. Out of these “alternativity markers”
readers of sf construct imaginary contexts (the future, “old futures” that have
been made obsolete and symbolic, alternative historical lines, parallel
universes, aliens, androids, utopias, etc.) that appear plausible.
Because sf’s language is so close to realistic discourse, it operates
vis-à-vis reading in general the way sf’s neologisms and neosemes (i.e., words
that have taken on new meanings) operate in normal sentences. Readers of sf need
to expend relatively little effort to activate the operations that Stockwell
finds most interesting in cognitive poetics: reference without referents,
construction of belief-frames and imaginary world building, large-scale
metaphors and models, neologisms and the back-filling of context—all of which
demonstrate the preferability of a synthetic social constructionist model of
both language and genre rather than a philological, historicist one.
I confess that, though I am professionally interested in the idea of a
poetics of sf, I don’t know much about linguistics, and I am never sure what the
word cognitive means when used in cognitive studies. (Sometimes it seems to
refer to thinking, sometimes to learning, sometimes to consciousness, but maybe
it’s something else altogether.) Stockwell’s argument is not reader-friendly
(well, friendly to me), which is surprising in a book so (theoretically)
reader-centered. Rather than presenting a sustained, progressive argument,
Stockwell zigzags between what he calls “Micrological” and “Macrological”
chapters, reflecting different levels of analysis—the Micrological chapters
focusing on the mechanics of language within texts, the Macrological on broader
historical, contextual connections. Each chapter also includes short sections
called “explorations” and “speculations” that act as assignments in
thought-experiment. (These thought-experiments are the most engaging parts of
Poetics, not incidentally bringing into relief Stockwell’s writerly power to
stimulate readers to do what readers do.)
Of his two tasks—using sf to illuminate linguistics and using linguistics to
illuminate sf—Stockwell is much more successful with the first. Many chapters
are barely more than expositions of rhetorical terminology, and Stockwell’s
reform taxonomy of deictic categories is mighty dry stuff. But he has a gift for
examples, and he draws on wide and informed readings of sf to illustrate his
ideas. For myself, the most useful thread is Stockwell’s exposition of sf’s use
of constitutive metaphors and their amplification into structural “architexts.”
Metaphors are mapping puzzles. They usually map something familiar onto
something unfamiliar, establishing that the two dissimilar structures are
isomorphic at some particularly meaningful, “salient” points. In sf Stockwell
also finds a different sort of metaphor where this relation is reversed, i.e.,
the unfamiliar is mapped onto the familiar, creating the sense of estrangement
and of creative construction simultaneously—as in the oft-invoked opening line
of Neuromancer (1984),“The sky above the port was the color of a
television tuned to a dead channel.”
The most readily accessible reading that resolves this metaphor is simply
that the sky is a grey colour. But the metaphor also suggests that televisions
are more basic and natural than sky. The “pathetic fallacy” of mainstream
literature, whereby nature imitates human emotions, is reversed so that nature
is alien and technology is familiar and comforting. This is further reinforced
by mapping the attribute of a capacity for life onto the “channel,” which is
“dead.” The potential for life is claimed for technology. (201-02)
In Stockwell’s view, sf characteristically produces constitutive isomorphisms,
metaphors in which “the isomorphism is seen as the only way to represent the
target concept” (203). These figures are particularly appropriate for describing
very abstract or unfamiliar objects. Here is where sf’s special cognitive power
comes into focus. Stockwell claims that sf readers’ familiarity with such
constitutive isomorphisms carries over into their imaginative engagement with
reality.
Since every science fictional text (by definition) has an element of
alternativity about it which differentiates it from our reality, any reading
of a science fiction narrative involves an act of generic isomorphism between
the real world and the text world. And if ... every isomorphism has the
capacity for re-framing our views of categories in the universe by being at
some level constitutive, then science fiction possesses a fundamentally
powerful capacity for altering readers’ perceptions and habits of
interpretation. If ... the “flow” of information in isomorphism is two-way and
interanimating, this means that the constitutive patterns in science fictional
reading are brought back to habits of reading and interpreting in reality.
(203)
Sf specializes in producing large-scale metaphoric structures that engage the
reader in mapping the whole text on the reader’s whole world. These architexts
configure “a fully worked-out, rich world, and also [provide] stylistic cues
that encourage a mapping of the whole textual universe with the reader’s
reality” (204). They are the utopias, dystopias, and apocalypses of sf. (Stockwell
also suggests yet another form of heterotopia, the ergodic architexts of games
and interactive fiction.)
The genre’s popularity and influence is an important aspect of its cognitive
status. They indicate that the cognitive work of reading sf does not require
elite training in interpreting complex texts. In developing this thread,
Stockwell reveals a streak of populist empiricism that is rather less useful and
persuasive than the textual thread.
The centrality of the reader is affirmed right at the start, when Stockwell
rejects any categorical definition that might have come from the critical
heavens. He applies instead Lakoff’s notion of the prototype effect: people
normally classify things by comparing them with prototypes they shape from their
experience. Sf, then, is a fluid concept that varies from person to person,
although it becomes increasingly refined as folks have more experience reading
sf: “different people will have different ideas of which texts count as science
fiction. Different readers will have different ideas of what criteria are more
or less important in that decision. And their decisions will depend on how much
experience they have of reading science fiction” (7). This begs the question of
what it is that readers are getting more experience of, but one can easily
answer it by supplying the consensus of masses of such readers. A fluid social
definition has a lot to recommend it, but there is always the risk of
exaggerating one part of a dialectic and distorting the whole picture.
Stockwell consistently voices his distaste for esoteric theories, educated
taste, postmodern criticism, and indeed for any writer-centered literary theory
that would grant authority to the folks producing the copy. Can authors really
be bracketed out of the creative process so thoroughly? As they read, don’t
readers also model the writer in their imaginations, using that model to
generate the sense of creativity and imagination as an active process? Stockwell
approaches style, the most author-centered aspect of writing, as a
social-historical question; the changes in sf style, from the “pulpstyle” to
cyberpunk, reflect changes in the audiences to which the texts were addressed.
His resistance to elitist literary values leads Stockwell into something of a
double-bind: for education (including a good course in linguistics) seems to
refine readers’ experience of the genre and their recognition of those
science-fictional qualities in texts that Stockwell’s book isolates. Despite the
populism of the prototype effect, The Poetics of Science Fiction is a disguised
book-length academic, indeed putatively scientific, definition of sf. (In one
rather strange section on sf styles, Stockwell describes an experiment he
conducted on some of his students to elicit the values they associated with
certain styles. The results demonstrate that educated students consider the
pulpstyle inferior and incompetent; they do not demonstrate, as Stockwell
implies, that this makes them elitist.)
The inspiration for much of Stockwell’s approach is Delany’s claim that sf is
capable of generating many more kinds of meaningful sentences than “mainstream”
or “mundane” literature. Neither Delany nor Stockwell ever clearly defines what
they consider to be “mainstream.” Delany often writes as if there were only two
kinds of sentences: sf and not-sf ( or “literature”); Stockwell, too, makes only
fleeting mentions of other specific genres. Such a crude, dualistic distinction
can have only limited benefit. Where does The Golden Ass (c. 150) fit in
this scheme? The Tempest ? Maldoror? Bleak House? The
Tin Drum? How do the sentences of surrealists, oneiric fantastists,
self-confessed mythomanes, hallucinators, ravers, and writers of the many fluid
hybrids of the fantastic compare with those of sf? This is less of a problem for
Stockwell than for Delany, since he finds sf useful precisely because it is so
similar to realism. (For Delany the whole distinction falls apart, when he
confesses to reading Jane Austen as if she were an sf writer.) Yet it is surely
time to think about sf with a richer conception of literature than this.
In a curt review in Foundation (#81 [Spring 2001]: 114-16), Patrick
Parrinder criticizes Stockwell for playing fast and loose with his material.
Treating poetics in purely descriptive and quasi-scientific linguistic terms and
ignoring the age-old topics of narrative and plot, mimesis, and dramatic action
is for Parrinder purely pseudo-scientific posturing. Parrinder is unfair, I
think—not mainly to Stockwell himself (who could have done a better job perhaps)
but to the very different notion of poetics that Stockwell derives from
cognitive linguistics. The relationship between models and metaphors has been
one of the most interesting areas of the philosophy of mind and science at least
since Max Black laid out the problem area in Models and Metaphors (1962).
Though the language and testing that cognitive linguists may use to analyze
these tropes may seem alien to aesthetics, the problem they describe is valuable
for understanding how people make sense of fictions in the first place.
“Cognitive poetics”—an oxymoron no more extreme than “science fiction”
itself—might be a bridge between the study of how people process information
into knowledge through conceptual tropes and how people construct meaning in
art. In The Poetics of Science Fiction, Peter Stockwell demonstrates that
sf can have an important role to play in that study.
Back to Home